Veblen Function
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions ( continuous strictly increasing
function Function or functionality may refer to: Computing * Function key, a type of key on computer keyboards * Function model, a structured representation of processes in a system * Function object or functor or functionoid, a concept of object-oriente ...
s from ordinals to ordinals), introduced by
Oswald Veblen Oswald Veblen (June 24, 1880 – August 10, 1960) was an American mathematician, geometer and topologist, whose work found application in atomic physics and the theory of relativity. He proved the Jordan curve theorem in 1905; while this was lon ...
in . If φ0 is any normal function, then for any non-zero ordinal α, φα is the function enumerating the common fixed points of φβ for β<α. These functions are all normal.


The Veblen hierarchy

In the special case when φ0(α)=ωα this family of functions is known as the Veblen hierarchy. The function φ1 is the same as the ε function: φ1(α)= εα. If \alpha < \beta \,, then \varphi_(\varphi_(\gamma)) = \varphi_(\gamma).M. Rathjen
Ordinal notations based on a weakly Mahlo cardinal
(1990, p.251). Accessed 16 August 2022.
From this and the fact that φβ is strictly increasing we get the ordering: \varphi_\alpha(\beta) < \varphi_\gamma(\delta) if and only if either (\alpha = \gamma and \beta < \delta ) or (\alpha < \gamma and \beta < \varphi_\gamma(\delta) ) or (\alpha > \gamma and \varphi_\alpha(\beta) < \delta ).


Fundamental sequences for the Veblen hierarchy

The fundamental sequence for an ordinal with
cofinality In mathematics, especially in order theory, the cofinality cf(''A'') of a partially ordered set ''A'' is the least of the cardinalities of the cofinal subsets of ''A''. This definition of cofinality relies on the axiom of choice, as it uses the ...
ω is a distinguished strictly increasing ω-sequence which has the ordinal as its limit. If one has fundamental sequences for α and all smaller limit ordinals, then one can create an explicit constructive bijection between ω and α, (i.e. one not using the axiom of choice). Here we will describe fundamental sequences for the Veblen hierarchy of ordinals. The image of ''n'' under the fundamental sequence for α will be indicated by α 'n'' A variation of Cantor normal form used in connection with the Veblen hierarchy is — every nonzero ordinal number α can be uniquely written as \alpha = \varphi_(\gamma_1) + \varphi_(\gamma_2) + \cdots + \varphi_(\gamma_k), where ''k''>0 is a natural number and each term after the first is less than or equal to the previous term, \varphi_(\gamma_m) \geq \varphi_(\gamma_) \,, and each \gamma_m < \varphi_(\gamma_m) \,. If a fundamental sequence can be provided for the last term, then that term can be replaced by such a sequence to get \alpha = \varphi_(\gamma_1) + \cdots + \varphi_(\gamma_) + (\varphi_(\gamma_k) \,. For any β, if γ is a limit with \gamma < \varphi_ (\gamma) \,, then let \varphi_(\gamma) = \varphi_(\gamma \,. No such sequence can be provided for \varphi_0(0) = ω0 = 1 because it does not have cofinality ω. For \varphi_0(\gamma+1) = \omega ^ = \omega^ \gamma \cdot \omega \,, we choose \varphi_0(\gamma+1) = \varphi_0(\gamma) \cdot n = \omega^ \cdot n \,. For \varphi_(0) \,, we use \varphi_(0) = 0 and \varphi_(0) +1= \varphi_(\varphi_(0) \,, i.e. 0, \varphi_(0), \varphi_(\varphi_(0)), etc.. For \varphi_(\gamma+1), we use \varphi_(\gamma+1) = \varphi_(\gamma)+1 and \varphi_(\gamma+1) +1= \varphi_ (\varphi_(\gamma+1) \,. Now suppose that β is a limit: If \beta < \varphi_(0), then let \varphi_(0) = \varphi_(0) \,. For \varphi_(\gamma+1), use \varphi_(\gamma+1) = \varphi_(\varphi_(\gamma)+1) \,. Otherwise, the ordinal cannot be described in terms of smaller ordinals using \varphi and this scheme does not apply to it.


The Γ function

The function Γ enumerates the ordinals α such that φα(0) = α. Γ0 is the
Feferman–Schütte ordinal In mathematics, the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0 is a large countable ordinal. It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theories, such as arithmetical transfinite recursion. It is named after Solomon Feferman and Kurt Schütte, ...
, i.e. it is the smallest α such that φα(0) = α. For Γ0, a fundamental sequence could be chosen to be \Gamma_0 = 0 and \Gamma_0 +1= \varphi_ (0) \,. For Γβ+1, let \Gamma_ = \Gamma_ + 1 and \Gamma_ +1= \varphi_ (0) \,. For Γβ where \beta < \Gamma_ is a limit, let \Gamma_ = \Gamma_ \,.


Generalizations


Finitely many variables

To build the Veblen function of a finite number of arguments (finitary Veblen function), let the binary function \varphi(\alpha, \gamma) be \varphi_\alpha(\gamma) as defined above. Let z be an empty string or a string consisting of one or more comma-separated zeros 0,0,...,0 and s be an empty string or a string consisting of one or more comma-separated ordinals \alpha _,\alpha _,...,\alpha _ with \alpha _>0. The binary function \varphi (\beta ,\gamma ) can be written as \varphi (s,\beta ,z,\gamma ) where both s and z are empty strings. The finitary Veblen functions are defined as follows: * \varphi (\gamma )=\omega ^ * \varphi (z,s,\gamma )=\varphi (s,\gamma ) * if \beta >0, then \varphi (s,\beta ,z,\gamma ) denotes the (1+\gamma )-th common fixed point of the functions \xi \mapsto \varphi (s,\delta ,\xi ,z) for each \delta <\beta For example, \varphi(1,0,\gamma) is the (1+\gamma)-th fixed point of the functions \xi\mapsto\varphi(\xi,0), namely \Gamma_\gamma; then \varphi(1,1,\gamma) enumerates the fixed points of that function, i.e., of the \xi\mapsto\Gamma_\xi function; and \varphi(2,0,\gamma) enumerates the fixed points of all the \xi\mapsto\varphi(1,\xi,0). Each instance of the generalized Veblen functions is continuous in the ''last nonzero'' variable (i.e., if one variable is made to vary and all later variables are kept constantly equal to zero). The ordinal \varphi(1,0,0,0) is sometimes known as the Ackermann ordinal. The limit of the \varphi(1,0,...,0) where the number of zeroes ranges over ω, is sometimes known as the "small" Veblen ordinal. Every non-zero ordinal \alpha less than the small Veblen ordinal (SVO) can be uniquely written in normal form for the finitary Veblen function: \alpha =\varphi (s_)+\varphi (s_)+\cdots +\varphi (s_) where * k is a positive integer * \varphi (s_)\geq \varphi (s_)\geq \cdots \geq \varphi (s_) * s_ is a string consisting of one or more comma-separated ordinals \alpha _,\alpha _,...,\alpha _ where \alpha _>0 and each \alpha _<\varphi (s_)


Fundamental sequences for limit ordinals of finitary Veblen function

For limit ordinals \alpha, written in normal form for the finitary Veblen function: * (\varphi(s_1)+\varphi(s_2)+\cdots+\varphi(s_k)) \varphi(s_1)+\varphi(s_2)+\cdots+\varphi(s_k) /math>, * \varphi(\gamma) \left\{\begin{array}{lcr} n \quad \text{if} \quad \gamma=1\\ \varphi(\gamma-1)\cdot n \quad \text{if} \quad \gamma \quad \text{is a successor ordinal}\\ \varphi(\gamma \quad \text{if} \quad \gamma \quad \text{is a limit ordinal}\\ \end{array}\right. , * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) 0 and \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) +1\varphi(s,\beta-1,\varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) z) if \gamma=0 and \beta is a successor ordinal, * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma-1)+1 and \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) +1\varphi(s,\beta-1,\varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) z) if \gamma and \beta are successor ordinals, * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma if \gamma is a limit ordinal, * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) \varphi(s,\beta z,\gamma) if \gamma=0 and \beta is a limit ordinal, * \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma) \varphi(s,\beta \varphi(s,\beta,z,\gamma-1)+1,z) if \gamma is a successor ordinal and \beta is a limit ordinal.


Transfinitely many variables

More generally, Veblen showed that φ can be defined even for a transfinite sequence of ordinals αβ, provided that all but a finite number of them are zero. Notice that if such a sequence of ordinals is chosen from those less than an uncountable
regular cardinal In set theory, a regular cardinal is a cardinal number that is equal to its own cofinality. More explicitly, this means that \kappa is a regular cardinal if and only if every unbounded subset C \subseteq \kappa has cardinality \kappa. Infinite ...
κ, then the sequence may be encoded as a single ordinal less than κκ (ordinal exponentiation). So one is defining a function φ from κκ into κ. The definition can be given as follows: let α be a transfinite sequence of ordinals (i.e., an ordinal function with finite support) ''which ends in zero'' (i.e., such that α0=0), and let α ³@0denote the same function where the final 0 has been replaced by γ. Then γ↦φ(α ³@0 is defined as the function enumerating the common fixed points of all functions ξ↦φ(β) where β ranges over all sequences which are obtained by decreasing the smallest-indexed nonzero value of α and replacing some smaller-indexed value with the indeterminate ξ (i.e., β=α ¶@ι0,ξ@ιmeaning that for the smallest index ι0 such that αι0 is nonzero the latter has been replaced by some value ζ<αι0 and that for some smaller index ι<ι0, the value αι=0 has been replaced with ξ). For example, if α=(1@ω) denotes the transfinite sequence with value 1 at ω and 0 everywhere else, then φ(1@ω) is the smallest fixed point of all the functions ξ↦φ(ξ,0,...,0) with finitely many final zeroes (it is also the limit of the φ(1,0,...,0) with finitely many zeroes, the small Veblen ordinal). The smallest ordinal α such that α is greater than φ applied to any function with support in α (i.e., which cannot be reached "from below" using the Veblen function of transfinitely many variables) is sometimes known as the "large" Veblen ordinal, or "great" Veblen number.


Values

The function takes on several prominent values: * \varphi(\omega,0), a bound on the order types of the recursive path orderings with finitely many function symbols. * The Feferman-Schutte ordinal \Gamma_0 is equal to \varphi(1,0,0). * The
small Veblen ordinal In mathematics, the small Veblen ordinal is a certain large countable ordinal, named after Oswald Veblen. It is occasionally called the Ackermann ordinal, though the Ackermann ordinal described by is somewhat smaller than the small Veblen ordina ...
is equal to \varphi\begin{pmatrix}1 \\ \omega\end{pmatrix}.


References

* Hilbert Levitz,
Transfinite Ordinals and Their Notations: For The Uninitiated
', expository article (8 pages, in PostScript) * * * * contains an informal description of the Veblen hierarchy. * *{{citation , jstor=2272243 , pages=439–459 , last1=Miller , first1=Larry W. , title=Normal Functions and Constructive Ordinal Notations , volume=41 , issue=2 , journal=The Journal of Symbolic Logic , year=1976 , doi=10.2307/2272243 Ordinal numbers Proof theory Hierarchy of functions